123456789101112131415161718192021222324252627282930313233343536373839404142434445464748495051525354555657585960616263646566676869707172737475767778798081828384858687888990919293949596979899100101102103104105106107108109110111112113114115116117118119120121122123124125126127128129130131132133134135136137138139140141142143144145146147148149150151152153154155156157158159160161162163164165166167168169170171172173174175176177178179180181182183184185186187188189190191192193194195196197198199200201202203204205206207208209210211212213214215216217218219220221222223224225226227228229230231232233234235236237238239240241242243244245246247248249250251252253254255256257258259260261262263264265266267268269270271272273274275276277278279280281282283284285286287288289290291292293294295296297298299300301302303304305306307308309310311312313314315316317318319320321322323324325326327328329330331332333334335336337338339340341342343344345346347348349350351352353354355356357358359360361362363364365366367368369370371372373374375376377378379380381382383384385386387388389390391392393394395396397398399400401402403404405406407408409410411412413414415416417418419420421422423424425426427428429 |
- September 2007In high school I decided I was going to study philosophy in college.
- I had several motives, some more honorable than others. One of the
- less honorable was to shock people. College was regarded as job
- training where I grew up, so studying philosophy seemed an impressively
- impractical thing to do. Sort of like slashing holes in your clothes
- or putting a safety pin through your ear, which were other forms
- of impressive impracticality then just coming into fashion.But I had some more honest motives as well. I thought studying
- philosophy would be a shortcut straight to wisdom. All the people
- majoring in other things would just end up with a bunch of domain
- knowledge. I would be learning what was really what.I'd tried to read a few philosophy books. Not recent ones; you
- wouldn't find those in our high school library. But I tried to
- read Plato and Aristotle. I doubt I believed I understood them,
- but they sounded like they were talking about something important.
- I assumed I'd learn what in college.The summer before senior year I took some college classes. I learned
- a lot in the calculus class, but I didn't learn much in Philosophy
- 101. And yet my plan to study philosophy remained intact. It was
- my fault I hadn't learned anything. I hadn't read the books we
- were assigned carefully enough. I'd give Berkeley's Principles
- of Human Knowledge another shot in college. Anything so admired
- and so difficult to read must have something in it, if one could
- only figure out what.Twenty-six years later, I still don't understand Berkeley. I have
- a nice edition of his collected works. Will I ever read it? Seems
- unlikely.The difference between then and now is that now I understand why
- Berkeley is probably not worth trying to understand. I think I see
- now what went wrong with philosophy, and how we might fix it.WordsI did end up being a philosophy major for most of college. It
- didn't work out as I'd hoped. I didn't learn any magical truths
- compared to which everything else was mere domain knowledge. But
- I do at least know now why I didn't. Philosophy doesn't really
- have a subject matter in the way math or history or most other
- university subjects do. There is no core of knowledge one must
- master. The closest you come to that is a knowledge of what various
- individual philosophers have said about different topics over the
- years. Few were sufficiently correct that people have forgotten
- who discovered what they discovered.Formal logic has some subject matter. I took several classes in
- logic. I don't know if I learned anything from them.
- [1]
- It does seem to me very important to be able to flip ideas around in
- one's head: to see when two ideas don't fully cover the space of
- possibilities, or when one idea is the same as another but with a
- couple things changed. But did studying logic teach me the importance
- of thinking this way, or make me any better at it? I don't know.There are things I know I learned from studying philosophy. The
- most dramatic I learned immediately, in the first semester of
- freshman year, in a class taught by Sydney Shoemaker. I learned
- that I don't exist. I am (and you are) a collection of cells that
- lurches around driven by various forces, and calls itself I. But
- there's no central, indivisible thing that your identity goes with.
- You could conceivably lose half your brain and live. Which means
- your brain could conceivably be split into two halves and each
- transplanted into different bodies. Imagine waking up after such
- an operation. You have to imagine being two people.The real lesson here is that the concepts we use in everyday life
- are fuzzy, and break down if pushed too hard. Even a concept as
- dear to us as I. It took me a while to grasp this, but when I
- did it was fairly sudden, like someone in the nineteenth century
- grasping evolution and realizing the story of creation they'd been
- told as a child was all wrong.
- [2]
- Outside of math there's a limit
- to how far you can push words; in fact, it would not be a bad
- definition of math to call it the study of terms that have precise
- meanings. Everyday words are inherently imprecise. They work well
- enough in everyday life that you don't notice. Words seem to work,
- just as Newtonian physics seems to. But you can always make them
- break if you push them far enough.I would say that this has been, unfortunately for philosophy, the
- central fact of philosophy. Most philosophical debates are not
- merely afflicted by but driven by confusions over words. Do we
- have free will? Depends what you mean by "free." Do abstract ideas
- exist? Depends what you mean by "exist."Wittgenstein is popularly credited with the idea that most philosophical
- controversies are due to confusions over language. I'm not sure
- how much credit to give him. I suspect a lot of people realized
- this, but reacted simply by not studying philosophy, rather than
- becoming philosophy professors.How did things get this way? Can something people have spent
- thousands of years studying really be a waste of time? Those are
- interesting questions. In fact, some of the most interesting
- questions you can ask about philosophy. The most valuable way to
- approach the current philosophical tradition may be neither to get
- lost in pointless speculations like Berkeley, nor to shut them down
- like Wittgenstein, but to study it as an example of reason gone
- wrong.HistoryWestern philosophy really begins with Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle.
- What we know of their predecessors comes from fragments and references
- in later works; their doctrines could be described as speculative
- cosmology that occasionally strays into analysis. Presumably they
- were driven by whatever makes people in every other society invent
- cosmologies.
- [3]With Socrates, Plato, and particularly Aristotle, this tradition
- turned a corner. There started to be a lot more analysis. I suspect
- Plato and Aristotle were encouraged in this by progress in math.
- Mathematicians had by then shown that you could figure things out
- in a much more conclusive way than by making up fine sounding stories
- about them.
- [4]People talk so much about abstractions now that we don't realize
- what a leap it must have been when they first started to. It was
- presumably many thousands of years between when people first started
- describing things as hot or cold and when someone asked "what is
- heat?" No doubt it was a very gradual process. We don't know if
- Plato or Aristotle were the first to ask any of the questions they
- did. But their works are the oldest we have that do this on a large
- scale, and there is a freshness (not to say naivete) about them
- that suggests some of the questions they asked were new to them,
- at least.Aristotle in particular reminds me of the phenomenon that happens
- when people discover something new, and are so excited by it that
- they race through a huge percentage of the newly discovered territory
- in one lifetime. If so, that's evidence of how new this kind of
- thinking was.
- [5]This is all to explain how Plato and Aristotle can be very impressive
- and yet naive and mistaken. It was impressive even to ask the
- questions they did. That doesn't mean they always came up with
- good answers. It's not considered insulting to say that ancient
- Greek mathematicians were naive in some respects, or at least lacked
- some concepts that would have made their lives easier. So I hope
- people will not be too offended if I propose that ancient philosophers
- were similarly naive. In particular, they don't seem to have fully
- grasped what I earlier called the central fact of philosophy: that
- words break if you push them too far."Much to the surprise of the builders of the first digital computers,"
- Rod Brooks wrote, "programs written for them usually did not work."
- [6]
- Something similar happened when people first started trying
- to talk about abstractions. Much to their surprise, they didn't
- arrive at answers they agreed upon. In fact, they rarely seemed
- to arrive at answers at all.They were in effect arguing about artifacts induced by sampling at
- too low a resolution.The proof of how useless some of their answers turned out to be is
- how little effect they have. No one after reading Aristotle's
- Metaphysics does anything differently as a result.
- [7]Surely I'm not claiming that ideas have to have practical applications
- to be interesting? No, they may not have to. Hardy's boast that
- number theory had no use whatsoever wouldn't disqualify it. But
- he turned out to be mistaken. In fact, it's suspiciously hard to
- find a field of math that truly has no practical use. And Aristotle's
- explanation of the ultimate goal of philosophy in Book A of the
- Metaphysics implies that philosophy should be useful too.Theoretical KnowledgeAristotle's goal was to find the most general of general principles.
- The examples he gives are convincing: an ordinary worker builds
- things a certain way out of habit; a master craftsman can do more
- because he grasps the underlying principles. The trend is clear:
- the more general the knowledge, the more admirable it is. But then
- he makes a mistake—possibly the most important mistake in the
- history of philosophy. He has noticed that theoretical knowledge
- is often acquired for its own sake, out of curiosity, rather than
- for any practical need. So he proposes there are two kinds of
- theoretical knowledge: some that's useful in practical matters and
- some that isn't. Since people interested in the latter are interested
- in it for its own sake, it must be more noble. So he sets as his
- goal in the Metaphysics the exploration of knowledge that has no
- practical use. Which means no alarms go off when he takes on grand
- but vaguely understood questions and ends up getting lost in a sea
- of words.His mistake was to confuse motive and result. Certainly, people
- who want a deep understanding of something are often driven by
- curiosity rather than any practical need. But that doesn't mean
- what they end up learning is useless. It's very valuable in practice
- to have a deep understanding of what you're doing; even if you're
- never called on to solve advanced problems, you can see shortcuts
- in the solution of simple ones, and your knowledge won't break down
- in edge cases, as it would if you were relying on formulas you
- didn't understand. Knowledge is power. That's what makes theoretical
- knowledge prestigious. It's also what causes smart people to be
- curious about certain things and not others; our DNA is not so
- disinterested as we might think.So while ideas don't have to have immediate practical applications
- to be interesting, the kinds of things we find interesting will
- surprisingly often turn out to have practical applications.The reason Aristotle didn't get anywhere in the Metaphysics was
- partly that he set off with contradictory aims: to explore the most
- abstract ideas, guided by the assumption that they were useless.
- He was like an explorer looking for a territory to the north of
- him, starting with the assumption that it was located to the south.And since his work became the map used by generations of future
- explorers, he sent them off in the wrong direction as well.
- [8]
- Perhaps worst of all, he protected them from both the criticism of
- outsiders and the promptings of their own inner compass by establishing
- the principle that the most noble sort of theoretical knowledge had
- to be useless.The Metaphysics is mostly a failed experiment. A few ideas from
- it turned out to be worth keeping; the bulk of it has had no effect
- at all. The Metaphysics is among the least read of all famous
- books. It's not hard to understand the way Newton's Principia
- is, but the way a garbled message is.Arguably it's an interesting failed experiment. But unfortunately
- that was not the conclusion Aristotle's successors derived from
- works like the Metaphysics.
- [9]
- Soon after, the western world
- fell on intellectual hard times. Instead of version 1s to be
- superseded, the works of Plato and Aristotle became revered texts
- to be mastered and discussed. And so things remained for a shockingly
- long time. It was not till around 1600 (in Europe, where the center
- of gravity had shifted by then) that one found people confident
- enough to treat Aristotle's work as a catalog of mistakes. And
- even then they rarely said so outright.If it seems surprising that the gap was so long, consider how little
- progress there was in math between Hellenistic times and the
- Renaissance.In the intervening years an unfortunate idea took hold: that it
- was not only acceptable to produce works like the Metaphysics,
- but that it was a particularly prestigious line of work, done by a
- class of people called philosophers. No one thought to go back and
- debug Aristotle's motivating argument. And so instead of correcting
- the problem Aristotle discovered by falling into it—that you can
- easily get lost if you talk too loosely about very abstract ideas—they
- continued to fall into it.The SingularityCuriously, however, the works they produced continued to attract
- new readers. Traditional philosophy occupies a kind of singularity
- in this respect. If you write in an unclear way about big ideas,
- you produce something that seems tantalizingly attractive to
- inexperienced but intellectually ambitious students. Till one knows
- better, it's hard to distinguish something that's hard to understand
- because the writer was unclear in his own mind from something like
- a mathematical proof that's hard to understand because the ideas
- it represents are hard to understand. To someone who hasn't learned
- the difference, traditional philosophy seems extremely attractive:
- as hard (and therefore impressive) as math, yet broader in scope.
- That was what lured me in as a high school student.This singularity is even more singular in having its own defense
- built in. When things are hard to understand, people who suspect
- they're nonsense generally keep quiet. There's no way to prove a
- text is meaningless. The closest you can get is to show that the
- official judges of some class of texts can't distinguish them from
- placebos.
- [10]And so instead of denouncing philosophy, most people who suspected
- it was a waste of time just studied other things. That alone is
- fairly damning evidence, considering philosophy's claims. It's
- supposed to be about the ultimate truths. Surely all smart people
- would be interested in it, if it delivered on that promise.Because philosophy's flaws turned away the sort of people who might
- have corrected them, they tended to be self-perpetuating. Bertrand
- Russell wrote in a letter in 1912:
- Hitherto the people attracted to philosophy have been mostly those
- who loved the big generalizations, which were all wrong, so that
- few people with exact minds have taken up the subject.
- [11]
- His response was to launch Wittgenstein at it, with dramatic results.I think Wittgenstein deserves to be famous not for the discovery
- that most previous philosophy was a waste of time, which judging
- from the circumstantial evidence must have been made by every smart
- person who studied a little philosophy and declined to pursue it
- further, but for how he acted in response.
- [12]
- Instead of quietly
- switching to another field, he made a fuss, from inside. He was
- Gorbachev.The field of philosophy is still shaken from the fright Wittgenstein
- gave it.
- [13]
- Later in life he spent a lot of time talking about
- how words worked. Since that seems to be allowed, that's what a
- lot of philosophers do now. Meanwhile, sensing a vacuum in the
- metaphysical speculation department, the people who used to do
- literary criticism have been edging Kantward, under new names like
- "literary theory," "critical theory," and when they're feeling
- ambitious, plain "theory." The writing is the familiar word salad:
- Gender is not like some of the other grammatical modes which
- express precisely a mode of conception without any reality that
- corresponds to the conceptual mode, and consequently do not express
- precisely something in reality by which the intellect could be
- moved to conceive a thing the way it does, even where that motive
- is not something in the thing as such.
- [14]
- The singularity I've described is not going away. There's a market
- for writing that sounds impressive and can't be disproven. There
- will always be both supply and demand. So if one group abandons
- this territory, there will always be others ready to occupy it.A ProposalWe may be able to do better. Here's an intriguing possibility.
- Perhaps we should do what Aristotle meant to do, instead of what
- he did. The goal he announces in the Metaphysics seems one worth
- pursuing: to discover the most general truths. That sounds good.
- But instead of trying to discover them because they're useless,
- let's try to discover them because they're useful.I propose we try again, but that we use that heretofore despised
- criterion, applicability, as a guide to keep us from wondering
- off into a swamp of abstractions. Instead of trying to answer the
- question:
- What are the most general truths?
- let's try to answer the question
- Of all the useful things we can say, which are the most general?
- The test of utility I propose is whether we cause people who read
- what we've written to do anything differently afterward. Knowing
- we have to give definite (if implicit) advice will keep us from
- straying beyond the resolution of the words we're using.The goal is the same as Aristotle's; we just approach it from a
- different direction.As an example of a useful, general idea, consider that of the
- controlled experiment. There's an idea that has turned out to be
- widely applicable. Some might say it's part of science, but it's
- not part of any specific science; it's literally meta-physics (in
- our sense of "meta"). The idea of evolution is another. It turns
- out to have quite broad applications—for example, in genetic
- algorithms and even product design. Frankfurt's distinction between
- lying and bullshitting seems a promising recent example.
- [15]These seem to me what philosophy should look like: quite general
- observations that would cause someone who understood them to do
- something differently.Such observations will necessarily be about things that are imprecisely
- defined. Once you start using words with precise meanings, you're
- doing math. So starting from utility won't entirely solve the
- problem I described above—it won't flush out the metaphysical
- singularity. But it should help. It gives people with good
- intentions a new roadmap into abstraction. And they may thereby
- produce things that make the writing of the people with bad intentions
- look bad by comparison.One drawback of this approach is that it won't produce the sort of
- writing that gets you tenure. And not just because it's not currently
- the fashion. In order to get tenure in any field you must not
- arrive at conclusions that members of tenure committees can disagree
- with. In practice there are two kinds of solutions to this problem.
- In math and the sciences, you can prove what you're saying, or at
- any rate adjust your conclusions so you're not claiming anything
- false ("6 of 8 subjects had lower blood pressure after the treatment").
- In the humanities you can either avoid drawing any definite conclusions
- (e.g. conclude that an issue is a complex one), or draw conclusions
- so narrow that no one cares enough to disagree with you.The kind of philosophy I'm advocating won't be able to take either
- of these routes. At best you'll be able to achieve the essayist's
- standard of proof, not the mathematician's or the experimentalist's.
- And yet you won't be able to meet the usefulness test without
- implying definite and fairly broadly applicable conclusions. Worse
- still, the usefulness test will tend to produce results that annoy
- people: there's no use in telling people things they already believe,
- and people are often upset to be told things they don't.Here's the exciting thing, though. Anyone can do this. Getting
- to general plus useful by starting with useful and cranking up the
- generality may be unsuitable for junior professors trying to get
- tenure, but it's better for everyone else, including professors who
- already have it. This side of the mountain is a nice gradual slope.
- You can start by writing things that are useful but very specific,
- and then gradually make them more general. Joe's has good burritos.
- What makes a good burrito? What makes good food? What makes
- anything good? You can take as long as you want. You don't have
- to get all the way to the top of the mountain. You don't have to
- tell anyone you're doing philosophy.If it seems like a daunting task to do philosophy, here's an
- encouraging thought. The field is a lot younger than it seems.
- Though the first philosophers in the western tradition lived about
- 2500 years ago, it would be misleading to say the field is 2500
- years old, because for most of that time the leading practitioners
- weren't doing much more than writing commentaries on Plato or
- Aristotle while watching over their shoulders for the next invading
- army. In the times when they weren't, philosophy was hopelessly
- intermingled with religion. It didn't shake itself free till a
- couple hundred years ago, and even then was afflicted by the
- structural problems I've described above. If I say this, some will
- say it's a ridiculously overbroad and uncharitable generalization,
- and others will say it's old news, but here goes: judging from their
- works, most philosophers up to the present have been wasting their
- time. So in a sense the field is still at the first step.
- [16]That sounds a preposterous claim to make. It won't seem so
- preposterous in 10,000 years. Civilization always seems old, because
- it's always the oldest it's ever been. The only way to say whether
- something is really old or not is by looking at structural evidence,
- and structurally philosophy is young; it's still reeling from the
- unexpected breakdown of words.Philosophy is as young now as math was in 1500. There is a lot
- more to discover.Notes
- [1]
- In practice formal logic is not much use, because despite
- some progress in the last 150 years we're still only able to formalize
- a small percentage of statements. We may never do that much better,
- for the same reason 1980s-style "knowledge representation" could
- never have worked; many statements may have no representation more
- concise than a huge, analog brain state.[2]
- It was harder for Darwin's contemporaries to grasp this than
- we can easily imagine. The story of creation in the Bible is not
- just a Judeo-Christian concept; it's roughly what everyone must
- have believed since before people were people. The hard part of
- grasping evolution was to realize that species weren't, as they
- seem to be, unchanging, but had instead evolved from different,
- simpler organisms over unimaginably long periods of time.Now we don't have to make that leap. No one in an industrialized
- country encounters the idea of evolution for the first time as an
- adult. Everyone's taught about it as a child, either as truth or
- heresy.[3]
- Greek philosophers before Plato wrote in verse. This must
- have affected what they said. If you try to write about the nature
- of the world in verse, it inevitably turns into incantation. Prose
- lets you be more precise, and more tentative.[4]
- Philosophy is like math's
- ne'er-do-well brother. It was born when Plato and Aristotle looked
- at the works of their predecessors and said in effect "why can't
- you be more like your brother?" Russell was still saying the same
- thing 2300 years later.Math is the precise half of the most abstract ideas, and philosophy
- the imprecise half. It's probably inevitable that philosophy will
- suffer by comparison, because there's no lower bound to its precision.
- Bad math is merely boring, whereas bad philosophy is nonsense. And
- yet there are some good ideas in the imprecise half.[5]
- Aristotle's best work was in logic and zoology, both of which
- he can be said to have invented. But the most dramatic departure
- from his predecessors was a new, much more analytical style of
- thinking. He was arguably the first scientist.[6]
- Brooks, Rodney, Programming in Common Lisp, Wiley, 1985, p.
- 94.[7]
- Some would say we depend on Aristotle more than we realize,
- because his ideas were one of the ingredients in our common culture.
- Certainly a lot of the words we use have a connection with Aristotle,
- but it seems a bit much to suggest that we wouldn't have the concept
- of the essence of something or the distinction between matter and
- form if Aristotle hadn't written about them.One way to see how much we really depend on Aristotle would be to
- diff European culture with Chinese: what ideas did European culture
- have in 1800 that Chinese culture didn't, in virtue of Aristotle's
- contribution?[8]
- The meaning of the word "philosophy" has changed over time.
- In ancient times it covered a broad range of topics, comparable in
- scope to our "scholarship" (though without the methodological
- implications). Even as late as Newton's time it included what we
- now call "science." But core of the subject today is still what
- seemed to Aristotle the core: the attempt to discover the most
- general truths.Aristotle didn't call this "metaphysics." That name got assigned
- to it because the books we now call the Metaphysics came after
- (meta = after) the Physics in the standard edition of Aristotle's
- works compiled by Andronicus of Rhodes three centuries later. What
- we call "metaphysics" Aristotle called "first philosophy."[9]
- Some of Aristotle's immediate successors may have realized
- this, but it's hard to say because most of their works are lost.[10]
- Sokal, Alan, "Transgressing the Boundaries: Toward a Transformative
- Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravity," Social Text 46/47, pp. 217-252.Abstract-sounding nonsense seems to be most attractive when it's
- aligned with some axe the audience already has to grind. If this
- is so we should find it's most popular with groups that are (or
- feel) weak. The powerful don't need its reassurance.[11]
- Letter to Ottoline Morrell, December 1912. Quoted in:Monk, Ray, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius, Penguin, 1991,
- p. 75.[12]
- A preliminary result, that all metaphysics between Aristotle
- and 1783 had been a waste of time, is due to I. Kant.[13]
- Wittgenstein asserted a sort of mastery to which the inhabitants
- of early 20th century Cambridge seem to have been peculiarly
- vulnerable—perhaps partly because so many had been raised religious
- and then stopped believing, so had a vacant space in their heads
- for someone to tell them what to do (others chose Marx or Cardinal
- Newman), and partly because a quiet, earnest place like Cambridge
- in that era had no natural immunity to messianic figures, just as
- European politics then had no natural immunity to dictators.[14]
- This is actually from the Ordinatio of Duns Scotus (ca.
- 1300), with "number" replaced by "gender." Plus ca change.Wolter, Allan (trans), Duns Scotus: Philosophical Writings, Nelson,
- 1963, p. 92.[15]
- Frankfurt, Harry, On Bullshit, Princeton University Press,
- 2005.[16]
- Some introductions to philosophy now take the line that
- philosophy is worth studying as a process rather than for any
- particular truths you'll learn. The philosophers whose works they
- cover would be rolling in their graves at that. They hoped they
- were doing more than serving as examples of how to argue: they hoped
- they were getting results. Most were wrong, but it doesn't seem
- an impossible hope.This argument seems to me like someone in 1500 looking at the lack
- of results achieved by alchemy and saying its value was as a process.
- No, they were going about it wrong. It turns out it is possible
- to transmute lead into gold (though not economically at current
- energy prices), but the route to that knowledge was to
- backtrack and try another approach.Thanks to Trevor Blackwell, Paul Buchheit, Jessica Livingston,
- Robert Morris, Mark Nitzberg, and Peter Norvig for reading drafts of this.
|